The New York Review of Books 

Volume 44, Number 6 … April 10, 1997 

(revised and enlarged according to the "version 2000"
"Imbalancing act: Jerome Bruner's cultural psychology"
, pp. 187-202, in: Clifford Geertz: Available light: anthropological reflections on philosophical topics. Princeton/N.J./USA 2000: Princeton University Press).

 

 

Review

Learning With Bruner 

By Clifford Geertz 

The Culture of Education
by Jerome Bruner
Harvard University Press, 224 pp., $24.95

 

Jerome Bruner by David Levine

1.

What does one say when one says "psychology": James, Wundt, Binet, or Pavlov? Freud, Lashley, Skinner, or Vygotsky? K–hler, Lewin, LÈvy-Bruhl, Bateson? Chomsky or Piaget? Daniel Dennett or Oliver Sacks? Herbert Simon? Since it got truly launched as a discipline and a profession in the last half of the nineteenth century, mainly by Germans, the self-proclaimed "science of the mind" has not just been troubled with a proliferation of theories, methods, arguments, and techniques. That was only to be expected. It has also been driven in wildly different directions by wildly different notions of what it is, as we say, "about"ówhat sort of knowledge, of what sort of reality, to what sort of end, it is supposed to produce. From the outside, at least, it does not look like a single field, divided into schools and specialties in the usual way. It looks like an assortment of disparate and disconnected inquiries classed together because they all make reference in some way or other to something or other called "mental functioning." Dozens of characters in search of a play.

From inside it doubtless looks a bit more ordered, if only because of the byzantine academic structure that has grown up around it (the American Psychological Association has forty-nine divisions), but surely no less miscellaneous. The wide swings between behaviorist, psychometric, cognitivist, depth psychological, topological, developmentalist, neurological, evolutionist, and culturalist conceptions of the subject have made being a psychologist an unsettled occupation, subject not only to fashion, as are all the human sciences, but also to sudden and frequent reversals of course. Paradigms, wholly new ways of going about things, come along not by the century, but by the decade; sometimes, it almost seems, by the month. It takes either a preternaturally focused, dogmatical person, who can shut out any ideas but his or her own, or a mercurial, hopelessly inquisitive one, who can keep dozens of them in play at once, to remain upright amid this tumble of programs, promises, and proclamations.

There are, in psychology, a great many more of the resolved and implacable, esprit de systËme types (Pavlov, Freud, Skinner, Piaget, Chomsky) than there are of the agile and adaptable, esprit de finesse ones (James, Bateson, Sacks). But it is among the latter that Jerome Bruner, author or coauthor of more than twenty books, and God knows how many articles, on almost as many subjects, clearly belongs. In a breathless, lurching, yet somehow deeply consecutive career spanning nearly sixty years, Bruner has brushed against almost every line of thought in psychology and transformed a number of them.

That career began at Harvard in the Forties, during the heyday of behaviorism, rat-running, the repetition of nonsense syllables, the discrimination of sensory differences, and the measurement of galvanic responses. But, dissatisfied with the piling up of experimental "findings" on peripheral matters (his first professional study involved conditioning "helplessness" in a rat imprisoned on an electrified grill), Bruner quickly joined the growing band of equally restless colleagues, within psychology and without, to become one of the leaders of the so-called "Cognitive Revolution."

By the late Fifties, this revolution was underway, and "bringing the mind back in" became the battle cry for a whole generation of psychologists, linguists, brain modelers, ethnologists, and computer scientists, as well as a few empirically minded philosophers. For them, the primary objects of study were not stimulus strengths and response patterns; they were mental actionsóattending, thinking, understanding, imagining, remembering, feeling, knowing. With a like-minded colleague, Bruner launched a famous series of "New Look" perception experiments to demonstrate the power of mental selectivity in seeing, hearing, and recognizing something. Poorer children see the same coin as larger than richer ones do; college students are either very much slower ("defensive") or very much quicker ("vigilant") to recognize threatening words than they are to recognize unthreatening ones.

With two of his students, he carried out a landmark study of abstract reasoning. How do people in fact, rather than in logic, test their hypotheses? How do they decide what is relevant to explanation and what is not? And in 1960, he and the psycholinguist George Miller, another restless soul, founded Harvard's interdisciplinary Center for Cognitive Studies, through which virtually all of the leading figures in the field, established or in the making, passed at one time or another, and which set off an explosion of similar centers and similar work both here and abroad. "We certainly generated a point of view, even a fad or two," Bruner wrote of his and his colleagues' work during this period in his (as it turns out, premature) 1983 autobiography, In Search of Mind. "About ideas, how can one tell?"[1]

After awhile Bruner himself became disenchanted with the Cognitive Revolution, or at least with what it had become. "That revolution," he wrote at the beginning of his 1990 Acts of Meaning, a "goodbye to all that" proclamation of a new direction,

was intended to bring "mind" back into the human sciences after a long cold winter of objectivismÖ. [But it] has now been diverted into issues that are marginal to the impulse that brought it into being. Indeed, it has been technicalized in a manner that even undermines that original impulse. This is not to say that it has failed: far from it, for cognitive science must surely be among the leading growth shares on the academic bourse. It may rather be that it has become diverted by success, a success whose technological virtuosity has cost dear. Some criticsÖeven argue that the new cognitive science, the child of the revolution, has gained its technical successes at the price of dehumanizing the very concept of mind it had sought to reestablish in psychology, and that it has thereby estranged much of psychology from the other human sciences and the humanities.[2]

In saving the Cognitive Revolution from itself, distancing it from high-tech reductionism (i.e., the brain is hardware, mind is software, thinking is the software processing digitalized information on the hardware), Bruner has raised over the last decade or so yet another banner heralding yet another dispensation: "Cultural Psychology." What now comes to the center of attention is the individual's engagement with established systems of shared meaning, with the beliefs, the values, and the understandings of those already in place in society as he or she is thrown in among them. For Bruner, the critical "test frame" for this point of view is educationóthe field of practices within which such engagement is, in the first instance, effected. Rather than a psychology that sees the mind as a programmable mechanism, we need one that sees it as a social achievement. Education is not simply a technical business of well-managed information processing, nor even simply a matter of applying "learning theories" to the classroom or using the results of subject-centered "achievement testing." It is a complex pursuit of fitting a culture to the needs of its members and their ways of knowing to the needs of the culture.[3]

2.

Bruner's concern with education and educational policy dates from the studies of mental development in infants and very young children that, in his growing resistance to machine cognitivism, he began to carry out in the mid-Sixties, justósuch are the workings of the Zeitgeistóas the Head Start program was coming, with Great Society fanfare, grandly into being. These studies led him to an "outside-in" view of such development, one which concerns itself with "the kind of world needed to make it possible to use mind (or heart!) effectivelyówhat kinds of symbol systems, what kinds of accounts of the past, what arts and sciencesÖ."[4] The unfolding of the critical features of human thinking, joint attention with others to objects and actions, attribution of beliefs, desires, and emotions to others, grasping the general significance of situations, a sense of selfhoodówhat Bruner calls "the entry into meaning"óbegins very early in the development process, prior not just to formal schooling but to walking and the acquisition of language. Infants, it turned out, were much smarter, more cognitively proactive rather than reactive, more attentive to the immediate social world around them, than had been previously suspected. They emphatically did not inhabit a world of "buzzing blooming confusion": they seemed to be in search of predictive stability from the very start.[5]

The Head Start program began with a rather different, in some ways complementary, in others contrasting, view of early development based on a rather different set of scientific investigations: those showing that laboratory animals raised in "impoverished environments," ones with few challenges and reduced stimulation, did less well than "normals" on such standard learning and problem-solving tasks as maze running and food finding. Transferred, more metaphorically than experimentally, to schooling and to school children, these inquiries led to the so-called "cultural deprivation hypothesis." Children raised in an "impoverished" cultural environment, in the ghetto, for example, would, for that reason, do less well in school. Hence the need for corrective action to enrich their environment early on, before the damage was done. Hence Head Start.

Aside from the fact that the idea of correcting for "cultural deprivation" depends on knowing what such deprivation consists in (what it has most often been taken to consist in is departure from the standards of an idealized, middle-class, "Ozzie and Harriet" American culture), such an approach seems to assume that "cultural enrichment" is a good to be provided to the deprived child by the wider society, like a hot lunch or a smallpox injection. The child is seen to be lacking something, not to be seeking something; regarded as receiving culture from elsewhere, not as constructing it in situ out of the materials and interactions immediately to hand. Bruner was a sometime advisor to Head Start, and he is still a defender of its very real successes and its possibilities for extension and reform (it is, after all, an "outside-in" program). But he argues that the results of his sort of research into the mental development of childrenógrown by now into a field in itself, turning up more and more evidence of the conceptual powers of the very youngórenders the "deprivation" approach obsolete. Seeing even the infant and the preschooler as active agents bent on mastery of a particular form of life, on developing a workable way of being in the world, demands a rethinking of the entire educational process. It is not so much a matter of providing something the child hasn't got as enabling something the child already has: the desire to make sense of self and others, the drive to understand what the devil is going on.

For Bruner, the critical enabling factor, the thing that brings the mind to focus, is cultureó"the way of life and thought that we construct, negotiate, institutionalize, and finally (after it's all settled) end up calling 'reality' to comfort ourselves."[6] Any theory of education that hopes to reform it, and there hardly is any other kind, needs to train its attention on the social production of meaning. The terms upon which society and childóthe "reality" already there and the scuttling intellect thrust bodily into itóengage one another are in good part worked out in the classroom, at least they are in our school-conscious society. It is there that mentality is most deliberately fashioned, subjectivity most systematically produced, and intersubjectivityóthe ability to "read other minds"ómost carefully nurtured. At least in the favorable case, not perhaps entirely common, the child, "seen as an epistemologist as well as a learner," moves into an ongoing community of discoursing adults and chattering children where "sheÖgradually comes to appreciate that she is acting not directly on 'the world' but on beliefs she holds about that world."[7]

This turn toward concern with the ways in which the understandings abroad in the larger society are used by the schoolchild to find his feet, to build up an inner sense of who he is, what others are up to, what is likely to happen, what can be done about things, opens Bruner's "cultural psychology" to a host of issues normally addressed by other disciplinesóhistory, literature, law, philosophy, linguistics, and most especially that other hopelessly miscellaneous and inconstant science, anthropology. Such a psychology, rather like anthropology, has an eclectic perspective and a vast ambition built directly into it. It seems to take all experience for its object, to draw on all scholarship for its means. With so many doors to open, and so many keys with which to open them, it would be folly to try to open all of them at once. That way lies knowing less and less about more and more. The door Bruner, sensitive as always to the practicalities of research, wants to open, not altogether surprisingly in view of recent developments in "discourse theory," "speech-act analysis," "the interpretation of cultures," and "the hermeneutics of everyday life," is narrative.

Telling stories, about ourselves and about others, to ourselves and to others, is "the most natural and the earliest way in which we organize our experience and our knowledge."[8] But you would hardly know it from standard educational theory, trained as it is upon tests and recipes:

It has been the convention of most schools to treat the arts of narrativeósong, drama, fiction, theater, whateveróas more "decoration" than necessity, as something with which to grace leisure, sometimes even as something morally exemplary. Despite that, we frame the accounts of our cultural ori-gins and our most cherished beliefs in story form, and it is not just the "content" of these stories that grip us, but their narrative artifice. Our immediate experience, what happened yesterday or the day before, is framed in the same storied way. Even more striking, we represent our lives (to ourselves as well as to others) in the form of narrative. It is not surprising that psychoanalysts now recognize that personhood implicates narrative, "neurosis" being a reflection of either an insufficient, incomplete, or inappropriate story about oneself. Recall that when Peter Pan asks Wendy to return to Never Never Land with him, he gives as his reason that she could teach the Lost Boys there how to tell stories. If they knew how to tell them, the Lost Boys might be able to grow up.[9]

Growing up among narratives, one's own, those of teachers, schoolmates, parents, janitors, and various other sorts of what Saul Bellow once mordantly referred to as "reality instructors," is the essential scene of educationó"We live in a sea of stories."[10] Learning how to swim in such a sea, how to construct stories, understand stories, classify stories, check out stories, see through stories, and use stories to find out how things work or what they come to, is what the school, and beyond the school the whole "culture of education," is, at base, all about. The heart of the matter, what the learner learns whatever the teacher teaches, is that "human beings make sense of the world by telling stories about itóby using the narrative mode for construing realityÖ."[11] Tales are tools, "instrument[s] of mind on behalf of meaning making."[12]

3.

Most of Bruner's book, a collection of essays and addresses rather than a systematic treatise, is 
[in the 00Aeng5-version: Bruner's most recent work is, then,] 
dedicated to tracing out the implications of this view of narrative as "both a mode of thought and an expression of a culture's world view."[13] There are inquiries into the teaching of science, into "folk pedagogy," into the collaborative nature of learning, and into the child's construction of "a theory of mind" to explain and understand other minds. Autism as the inability to develop such a theory, the formal features of narrative, culture as praxis, and the approaches to education of Vygotsky, Piaget, and Pierre Bourdieu, related to Bruner's but in some tension with it, are all discussed. So are recent developments in primatology, cross-cultural studies of education, IQ testing, the role of the teacher, "metacognition" ("thinking about one's thinking"), relativism, and the uses of neurology. It is all rather on the wing; a wondrous lot goes by wondrously fast.

This is not that serious a fault in a series of forays designed to open up a territory rather than to chart and settle it. But it does leave even the sympathetic reader at a bit of a loss to discover where it all is going, what "cultural psychology" amounts to as a field among fields, a continuing enterprise with a budget of issues and an agenda for confronting them. One can, of course, get something of a sense of this by looking up Bruner's dozens upon dozens of technical investigations or by hunting down his even more numerous citations to studies by colleagues on everything from "the child's understanding of number" and "oral versions of personal experience" to "benefit-cost analysis of pre-school education" and "impaired recognition of emotion in facial expression following bilateral damage to the human amygdala."

But since most of this "literature," wrapped in statistics and enfolded in protocols, is scattered through professional journals and disciplinary symposia, few besides specialists are likely to find the patience for such a task. Genuine treatises, more summary and thus more accessible synthesizing works, written by students, co-workers, and followers of Bruner, are beginning to appear in increasing numbers, and from them one can get a somewhat clearer picture of where the whole enterprise is at the moment and what progress it is making.[14] And in the final chapter of this book, called, with uncertain surety, "Psychology's Next Chapter," Bruner himself undertakes to lay out the directions in which cultural psychology should move and to describe how it should relate itself to other approaches to "the study of mind."

As usual, his attitude is conciliatory, eclectic, energetic, upbeat:

Can a cultural psychologyÖsimply stand apart from the kind of biologically rooted, individually oriented, laboratory dominated psychology that we have known in the past? Must the more situated study of mind-in-culture, more interpretively anthropological in spirit, jettison all that we have learned before? Some writersÖ propose that our past was a mistake, a misunderstanding of what psychology is aboutÖ. [But] I would like to urge an end to [an] "either-or" approach to the question of what psychology should be in the future, whether it should be entirely biological, exclusively computational, or monopolistically cultural.

He wants to show how

psychology can, by devoting its attention to certain critical topics, Öillustrate the interaction of biological, evolutionary, individual psychological, and cultural insights in helping us grasp the nature of human mental functioning. [The] "next chapter" in psychology [will be] about "intersubjectivity"óhow people come to know what others have in mind and how they adjust accordinglyÖa set of topicsÖcentral to any viable conception of a cultural psychology. But it cannot be understood without reference to primate evolution, to neural functioning, and to the processing capacities of minds.[15] 

This is all very well, the sort of balanced and reasonable approach that softens contrasts, disarms enemies, skirts difficulties, and finesses hard decisions. But there remains the sense that Bruner is underestimating theexplosiveness of his own ideas. To argue that culture is socially and historically constructed; that narrative is a primary, in humans perhaps the primary, mode of knowing; that we assemble the selves we live in out of materials lying about in the society around us and develop "a theory of mind" to comprehend the selves of others; that we act not directly on the world but on beliefs we hold about the world; that from birth on we are all active, impassioned "meaning makers" in search of plausible stories; and that "mind cannot in any sense be regarded as 'natural' or naked, with culture thought of as an add-on"ósuch a view amounts to rather more than a mid-course correction.[16]  Taken all in all, it amounts to adopting a position that can fairly be called radical, not to say subversive. It seems very doubtful that such views, and others connected with themóperspectivism, instrumentalism, contextualism, anti-reductionismócan be absorbed into the ongoing traditions of psychological research (or indeed into the human sciences generally) without causing a fair amount of noise and upheaval. If "Cultural Psychology" does gain ascendancy, or even serious market share, it will disturb a lot more than pedagogy.

For it is in fact the case that not only is cultural psychology evolving rapidly, gathering force, and amassing evidence, but so as well are its two most important rivals, or anyway alternativesóinformation-processing cognitivism and neurobiological reductionism. The introduction into the first of distributive parallel processing (which Bruner dismisses at one point as but a "veiled version" of behaviorist associationism)[17] and computer-mediated experimentalismóinteractive video and artificial activity systemsóhas given it something of a second wind. A technology-driven spurt in brain research, the extension of evolutionary theory to everything from morality to consciousness, the emergence of a whole range of post-Cartesian philosophies of mind, and perhaps most important the dawning of the age of the absolute gene, have done the same for the second. In the face of all this, and of the moral and practical issues at stake, courteous, to-each-his-own dividing up of the territory does not look to be in the cards.

"Psychology's Next Chapter" is more likely to be tumultuous than irenic as computational, biological, and cultural approaches grow in sophistication and power sufficient enough to assure that they will have transformative impacts upon one another. The simple assertion that biology provides "constraints" upon culture, as it does, and that computationally based cognitive science is incompetent to deal with "the messiness of meaning making," as it is, will hardly suffice to resolve the deep issues that, by its very presence, cultural psychology is going to make unavoidable. Bringing so large and misshapen a camel as anthropology into psychology's tent is going to do more to toss things around than to arrange them in order. At the climax of what is surely one of the most extraordinary and productive careers in the human sciences, a career of continuous originality and tireless exploration, Jerome Bruner may have produced a more revolutionary revolution than even he altogether appreciates.

[the following final text is contained only in the 2000 version:]

Within anthropology, the clarity, the relevance, the analytic power, even the moral status of the concept of culture have been much discussed in recent years, to no very certain conclusion save that if it is not to be discarded as an imperialist relic, an ideological ma/ neuver, or a popular catchword, as its various critics variously sug/ gest, it must be seriously rethought. Giving it a central role in ìpsy/ chology's next chapter,î as Bruner suggests, should do much to encourage such rethinking, as well as to extend similar questionings to the no less embattled concept of mind he wishes to conjoin with it. But it will hardly simplify things. To the abiding puzzles afflicting psychologyónature and nurture, top down and bottom up, reason and passion, conscious and unconscious, competence and perfor/ mance, privacy and intersubjectivity, experience and behavior, learning and forgettingówill be added a host of new ones: meaning and action, social causality and personal intention, relativism and universalism, and, perhaps most fundamentally, difference and com/ monality. If anthropology is obsessed with anything, it is with how much difference difference makes.

There is no simple answer to this question so far as cultural differences are concerned (though simple answers are often enough given, usually extreme). In anthropology, there is merely the ques/ tion itself, asked and reasked in every instance. To throw so singu/ larizing a science in among such determinedly generalizing ones as genetics, information processing, developmental psychology, genera/ tive grammar, neurology, decision theory, and neo-Darwinism is to court terminal confusion in a realmóthe study of mental activityó already well-enough obscured by imperial programs, inimical world views, and a proliferation of procedures. What, in the days of Sartre, we would have called Bruner's ìprojectî implies a good deal more than adding ìcultureî (or ìmeaning,î or ìnarrativeî) to the mixó another variable heard from. It implies, as he himself has said, con/ fronting the world as a field of differences, ìadjudicating the differ/ ent construals of reality that are inevitable in any diverse society.î [18]

Or in any genuine inquiry. Trying to bring together, or perhaps more carefully, to relate in a productive manner, everything from ìpsychic universalsî and ìstory tellingî to ìneural modelsî and ìen/ culturated chimpanzees,î from Vygotsky, Goodman, and Bartlett to Edelman, Simon, and Premack (not to speak of Geertz and LÈvi/ Strauss!) obviously involves as much mobilizing differences as it does dissolving them, ìadjudicatingî contrasts (not, perhaps, alto/ gether the best word), rather than overriding them or forcing them into some pallid, feel-good ecumenical whole. It may just be that it is not the reconciliation of diverse approaches to the study of mind that is most immediately needed, a calming eclecticism, but the effective playing of them off against one another. If that miraculous cabbage, the brain itself, now appears to be more adequately under/ stood in terms of separated processes simultaneously active, then the same may be true of the mind with which biologizers so often con/ fuse it. History, culture, the body, and the workings of the physical world indeed fix the character of anyone's mental lifeóshape it, stabilize it, fill it with content. But they do so independently, par/ titively, concurrently, and differentially. They do not just disappear into a resultant like so many component vectors, or come together in some nicely equilibrated frictionless concord.

Such a view, that a useful understanding of how we manage to think must be one in which symbolic forms, historical traditions, cultural artifacts, neural codes, environmental pressures, genetic in/ scriptions, and the like operate coactively, often enough even ago/ nistically, seems to be struggling toward exacter expression in recent work, at least in part stimulated by Bruner's own. Andy Clark's Be/ ing There is dedicated to nothing less than ìputting brain, body and world together again.î William Frawley's Vygotsky and Cognitive Sci/ ence seeks ìto show that the human mind is both a social construct and a computational device as opposed to one or the other.î [19] So far as culture (ìthe symbolic systems that individuals [use] in construct/ ing meaningî) is concerned, what Clark calls ìthe image of mind as inextricably interwoven with body, world and action,î and Frawley, ìthe mind in the world [and] the world Ö in the mind,î makes it impossible to regard it any longer as external and supplementary to the resident powers of the human intellect, a tool or a prosthesis. It is ingredient in those powers.[20]

The course of our understanding of mind does not consist in a determined march toward an omega point where everything finally falls happily together; it consists in the repeated deployment of dis/ tinct inquiries in such a way that, again and again, apparently with/ out end, they force deep-going reconsiderations upon one another. Constructing a powerful ìcultural psychologyî (or a powerful psy/ chological anthropologyónot altogether the same thing) is less a matter of hybridizing disciplines, putting hyphens between them, than it is of reciprocally disequilibrating them. At a time when monomanic, theory-of-everything conceptions of mental function/ ing, stimulated by local developments in neurology, genetics, pri/ matology, literary theory, semiotics, systems theory, robotics, or whatever have come increasingly into fashion, what seems to be needed is the development of strategies for enabling Bruner's ìdiffer/ ent construals of [mental] realityî to confront, discompose, energize, and deprovincialize one another, and thus drive the enterprise errat/ ically onward. Everything that rises need not converge: it has only to make the most of its incorrigible diversity.

The ways of doing this, of making disparate, even conflicting, views of what the mind is, how it works, and how it is most profita/ bly studied into useful correctives to one another's assurances, are, of course, themselves multipleóextremely difficult to devise, ex/ tremely difficult to put in place once they are devised, extremely 

susceptible, once they are put in place, to bringing on an academic version of Hobbsean war. Again, so far as anthropology is con/ cerned, what most positions it to contribute to such a task, and to avoiding its pathological outcomes, is not its particular findings about African witchcraft or Melanesian exchange, and certainly not any theories it may have developed about universal necessities and the ingenerate logic of social life, but its long and intimate engage/ ment with cultural difference and with the concrete workings of such difference in social life. Surveying contrasts, tracing their im/ plications, and enabling them somehow to speak to general issues is, after all, its metier.

Managing difference, or if that sounds too manipulative, navi/ gating it, is the heart of the matter. As with all such enterprises, there are a good many more ways of getting it wrong than there are of getting it right, and one of the most common ways of getting it wrong is through convincing ourselves that we have gotten it rightóconsciousness explained, how the mind works, the engine of reason, the last word. Whitehead once remarked that we must build our systems and keep them open; but, given his own passion for completeness, certainty, and wholistic synthesis, he neglected to add that the former is a great deal easier to accomplish than the latter. The hedgehog's disease and the fox'sópremature closure and the obsessive fear of it, tying it all up and letting it all dangleómay be equally obstructive of movement in the human sciences. But, ìin nature,î as the positivists used to say, the one is encountered far more frequently than the other, especially in these days of high-tech tunnel vision.

One thing that is certain, if anything is certain when one comes to talk of such things as meaning, consciousness, thought, and feel/ ing, is that both psychology's ìnext chapterî and anthropology's are not going to be orderly, well-formed sorts of discourse, beginnings and middles neatly connected to ends. Neither isolating rival ap/ proaches to understanding mind and culture in fenced communities (ìevolutionary psychology,î ìsymbolic anthropologyî) nor fusing them into an inclusive whole (ìcognitive science,î ìsemioticsî) is in the long run, or even the medium, really workableóthe one be/ cause it reifies difference and exalts it, the other because it under/ estimates its ubiquity, its ineradicability, and its force.

The reason that the legalism ìadjudicationî may not be the best term to signal the alternative to these ways of avoiding issues is that it suggests an ìadjudicator,î something (or someone) that sorts things out, that reconciles approaches, ranks them, or chooses among them. But whatever order emerges in either mind or culture, it is not produced by some regnant central process or directive structure; it is produced by the play of Ö well, whatever it is that is, in the case, in play. The future of cultural psychology depends on the ability of its practitioners to capitalize on so turbulent and inel/ egant a situationóa situation in which the openness, responsive/ ness, adaptability, inventiveness, and intellectual restlessness, to say nothing of the optimism, that have characterized Bruner's work since its beginnings are peculiarly well-suited. His outlook and his example seem likely to flourish, whoever it is who continues the narrative, and whatever it is that it turns out to say.

Notes

1

J. Bruner, In Search of Mind, Essays in Autobiography, New York: Harper and Row, 1983, p. 126.

2

J. Bruner, Acts of Meaning, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990, p. 1.

3

[footnotes 3 - 13 only in the 2000 version]

J. Bruner, The Culture of Education, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996, p. 43.

4

Ibid., p. 9.

5

Ibid., pp. 71ñ72.

6

Ibid., p. 87.

7

Ibid., pp. 57, 49.

8

Ibid., p. 121.

9

Ibid., p. 40.

10

Ibid., p. 147.

11

Ibid., p. 130.

12

Ibid., p. 41.

13

Ibid., p. xiv.

14

[= FN 3 in the 1997 version]

Two such works have just now emerged: M. Cole, Cultural Psychology, A Once and Future Discipline, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996, and B. Shore, Culture in Mind, Cognition, Culture, and the Problem of Meaning, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996. Cole, a developmental psychologist moving toward social anthropology, traces the history of cross-cultural research in psychology, in which he has himself played a major role, and develops a conceptual framework for the integration of anthropological and psychological inquiry based on "the romantic science" ("the dream of a novelist and a scientist combined") of the Russian psychologists Alexei Leontiev, Alexander Luria, and Lev Vygotsky. Shore, a social anthropologist moving toward cognitive psychology, considers some classical ethnographic studies, including his own on Samoa, as well as various contemporary cultural formsóbaseball, interior decorating, air travelóin an effort to relate what he calls "personal" (that is, "cognitive") and "conventional" (that is, "cultural") mental models to each other and thus break down the long and unfortunate separation of anthropology and psychology. 

Both these books bite off a good deal more than they can chew, and neither coheres very well; but they offer valuable accounts of the present state of play. For other such summary works, equally useful for getting a hands-on sense of the field and its prospects, see R.A. Shweder, Thinking through Cultures: Expeditions in Cultural Psychology (Harvard University Press, 1991); J. Stigler, R.A. Shweder, and G. Herdt, editors, Cultural Psychology: Essays on Comparative Human Development (Cambridge University Press, 1989); and R.A. Shweder and R.A. Levine, editors, Culture Theory: Essays on Mind, Self, and Emotion (Cambridge University Press, 1984).

15

[footnotes 15 & 16 only in the 2000 version]

Bruner, The Culture of Education, p. 160.

16

Ibid., p. 171.

17

[this footnote as FN 4 only in the 1997 version]

In distributive parallel processing, information is not processed serially, one stage after another along a line to a final output, as it is in ordinary computers; it is apportioned among different sorts of interlinked processing units, which process it simultaneously to produce a joint output. This provides various advantages (and disadvantages) in message transmission, and permits somewhat more persuasive accounts of some aspects of nervous-system functioning. But whether it overcomes the obstacles facing computer models of the mind remains a matter of intense dispute.

18

Bruner, Acts of Meaning, p. 95.

19

A. Clark, Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again, Cambridge: MIT Press, 1997; W. Frawley, Vygotsky and Cognitive Science: Lan/ guage and the Unification of the Social and Computational Mind, Cambridge: Har/ vard University Press, 1997. For acknowledgments of the stimulus of Bruner's work, see, eg., Clark, p. 25; Frawley, p. 223.

20

Bruner, Acts of Meaning, p. 11; Clark, Being There, p. xvii; Frawley, Vygotsky and Cognitive Science, p. 295. For a constitutive as opposed to an add/ on view of the role of culture in human evolution, see Clifford Geertz, ìThe Impact of the Concept of Culture on the Concept of Manî and ìThe Growth of Culture and the Evolution of Mind,î in The Interpretation of Cultures, New York: Basic Books, 1973, pp. 33ñ54, 55ñ83.

 


Learning with Bruner: the new psychology, in: The New York Review of Books (New-York/N.Y./USA: A. W. Ellsworth, etc.), vol. 44 no. 6 (April 10, 1997), pp. 22-24 (= version 1997).


Imbalancing act: Jerome Bruner's cultural psychology, in: Available light: anthropological reflections on philosophical topics. Princeton/N.J./USA: Princeton University Press, pp. 187-202 (= version 2000).


 

online sources: 
http://www.nybooks.com/articles/article-preview?article_id=1222
.

(corrected & enlarged by) http://www.questia.com/PM.qst?a=o&d=99830258

 


Using this text is also subject to the general HyperGeertz-Copyright-regulations based on Austrian copyright-law (2001), which - in short - allow a personal, nonprofit & educational (all must apply) use of material stored in data bases, including a restricted redistribution of such material, if this is also for nonprofit purposes and restricted to the scientific community (both must apply), and if full and accurate attribution to the author, original source and date of publication, web location(s) or originating list(s) is given ("fair-use-restriction"). Any other use transgressing this restriction is subject to a direct agreement between a subsequent user and the holder of the original copyright(s) as indicated by the source(s). HyperGeertz@WorldCatalogue cannot be held responsible for any neglection of these regulations and will impose such a responsibility on any unlawful user.

Each copy of any part of a  transmission of a HyperGeertz-Text must therefore contain this same copyright notice as it appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission, including any specific copyright notice as  indicated above by the original copyright holder and/ or the previous online source(s).